Science and Philosophy on FREE WILL (Purpose – 3)
Scientists think they can prove that free will is an
illusion. Philosophers are urging them to think again.
In
2007, Haynes, a neuroscientist at the Bernstein Center for Computational
Neuroscience in Berlin, put people into a brain scanner in which a display
screen flashed a succession of random letters. He told them to press a button with
either their right or left index fingers whenever they felt the urge, and to
remember the letter that was showing on the screen when they made the decision.
The experiment used functional magnetic resonance imaging (fMRI) to reveal
brain activity in real time as the volunteers chose to use their right or left
hands. The results were quite a surprise.
"The
first thought we had was 'we have to check if this is real'," says Haynes.
"We came up with more sanity checks than I've ever seen in any other study
before."
The
conscious decision to push the button was made about a second before the actual
act, but the team discovered that a pattern of brain activity seemed to predict
that decision by as many as seven seconds. Long before the subjects were even
aware of making a choice, it seems, their brains had already decided.
As humans, we like to think that our decisions are under our
conscious control — that we have free will. Philosophers have debated that
concept for centuries, and now Haynes and other experimental neuroscientists
are raising a new challenge. They argue that consciousness of a decision may be
a mere biochemical afterthought, with no influence whatsoever on a person's
actions. According to this logic, they say, free will is an illusion. "We
feel we choose, but we don't," says Patrick Haggard, a neuroscientist at
University College London.
You may have thought you decided whether to have tea or
coffee this morning, for example, but the decision may have been made long
before you were aware of it.
Philosophers aren't convinced that brain scans can demolish
free will so easily. Some have questioned the neuroscientists' results and
interpretations, arguing that the researchers have not quite grasped the
concept that they are ridiculing. Many more don't engage with
scientists at all.
Neuroscientists and philosophers are talking about different
subjects, whilst they believe they are talking about the same thing. Such a
remark is passed by Walter Glannon, a philosopher at the University of Calgary
in Canada, who has interests in neuroscience, ethics and free will.
There are some signs that this is beginning to change. This
month, a lot of projects will get under way as part of Big Questions in
Free Will, a four-year US$4.4-million program funded by the John Templeton
Foundation in, Pennsylvania, which supports research bridging theology,
philosophy and natural science. Some say that, with refined experiments,
neuroscience could help researchers to identify the physical processes
underlying conscious intention and to better understand the brain activity that
precedes it. And if unconscious brain activity could be found to predict
decisions perfectly, the work really could confuse the notion of free will. A possibility
that what are now correlations could at some point become causal connections
between brain mechanisms and behaviors is expressed by Glannon (philosopher).
In such a situation it would threaten the concept of free will by philosophers,
he further feels.
Pointing out that Haynes and his team could predict a left
or right button press with only 60% accuracy at best the critics raised their
objection. Although better than chance, this isn't enough to claim that you can
see the brain making its mind up before conscious awareness, argues Adina
Roskies, a neuroscientist and philosopher who works on free will at Dartmouth
College in Hanover, New Hampshire. Besides, "all it suggests is that there
are some physical factors that influence decision-making", which shouldn't
be surprising. Philosophers who know about the science, she adds, don't think
this sort of study is good evidence for the absence of free will, because the
experiments are caricatures (mockery, distortion) of decision-making. Even the
seemingly simple decision of whether to have tea or coffee is more complex than
deciding whether to push a button with one hand or the other.
Philosophers question the assumptions underlying such
interpretations. "Part of what's driving some of these conclusions is the
thought that free will has to be spiritual or involve souls or something,"
says Al Mele, a philosopher at Florida State University. If neuroscientists
find unconscious neural activity that drives decision-making, the troublesome
concept of mind as separate from body disappears, as doe’s free will. This
'dualist' conception of free will is an easy target for neuroscientists to
knock down, says Glannon (philosopher). "Neatly dividing mind and brain makes
it easier for neuroscientists to drive a wedge between them," he adds. (Spoil
the relationship between two)
The trouble is, most current philosophers don't think about
free will like that, says Mele. Many are materialists — believing that
everything has a physical basis, and decisions and actions come from brain
activity. So scientists are weighing in on a notion that philosophers consider
irrelevant.
Nowadays, says Mele (philosopher Alfred Mele, professor
at Florida State University, having a long standing research on the concept
of FREE WILL); the majority of philosophers are comfortable with the idea
that people can make rational decisions in a deterministic universe. They
debate the interplay between freedom and determinism — the theory that
everything is predestined, either by fate or by physical laws. But Roskies (Adina
Roskies, Department of Philosophy, Dartmouth College, Hanover), says that
results from neuroscience can't yet settle that debate.
They may speak to the
predictability of actions, but not to the issue of determinism.
Neuroscientists also sometimes have misconceptions about
their own field, says Michael Gazzaniga, a neuroscientist at the University of
California, Santa Barbara. In particular, scientists tend to see preparatory
brain activity as proceeding step wise, one bit at a time, to a final decision.
He suggests that researchers should instead think of processes working in
parallel, in a complex network with interactions happening continually. The
time at which one becomes aware of a decision is thus not as important as some
have thought.
There are conceptual issues — and then there is semantics
(study of meaning or interpretation). "What would really help is if
scientists and philosophers could come to an agreement on what free will
means," says Glannon. Even within philosophy, definitions of free will
don't always match up. Some philosophers define it as the ability to make
rational decisions in the absence of coercion (threatening). Some definitions
place it in cosmic (universal) context: at the moment of decision, given
everything that's happened in the past, it is possible to reach a different
decision. Others stick to the idea that a non-physical 'soul' is directing
decisions.
Neuroscience could contribute directly to tidying up (bring
order, straighten) definitions, or adding an empirical (experimentally
provable) dimension to them. It might lead to a deeper, better understanding of
what freely willing something involves, or refine views of what conscious intention
is, says Roskies.
Mele is directing the Templeton Foundation project that is
beginning to bring philosophers and neuroscientists together. "I think if
we do a new generation of studies with better design, we'll get better evidence
about what goes on in the brain when people make decisions," he says.
Philosophers are willing to admit that neuroscience could
one day trouble the concept of free will. Imagine a situation (philosophers
like to do this) in which researchers could always predict what someone would
decide from their brain activity, before the subject became aware of their
decision. "If that turned out to be true, that would be a threat to free
will," says Mele. Still, even those who have perhaps prematurely
proclaimed (openly declare) the death of free will agree that such results
would have to be replicated on many different levels of decision-making.
Pressing a button or playing a game is far removed from (very different from)
making a cup of tea, running for president or committing a crime.
The practical effects of demolishing free will are hard to
predict. Biological determinism doesn't hold up as a defense in law. Legal
scholars aren't ready to ditch (discard) the principle of personal
responsibility. "The law has to be based on the idea that people are
responsible for their actions, except in exceptional circumstances," says
Nicholas Mackintosh, director of a project on neuroscience and the law; run by
the Royal Society in London.
Mele is hopeful that other philosophers will become better acquainted
with the science of conscious intention. And where philosophy is concerned, he
says, scientists would do well to soften their stance. "It's not as though
the task of neuroscientists who work on free will has to be to show there isn't
any."
It seems that the areas which require immediate attention
are:
Even within philosophy, definitions of free will don't
always match up
Agreement on what free will means does not exist.
Definition of FREE WILL not spelled.
Neuroscientists also sometimes have misconceptions about
their own field
Bringing philosophers and neuroscientists together and developing
approach toward each other with softened, positive attitude. (Ego less approach
to search the Truth).
The will (desire) of the Templeton foundation to progress
the work on FREE WILL thus appears to depends upon the attitude (intent) of the
academicians in defining the terms of reference and developing a positive
approach towards the problem with the aim for the search of TRUTH and not
nurturing the subjective interests.
The ‘desire’, ‘intention’, ‘attitude’, (and also ego), to a
layman they are the faculties of Mind. Academicians are not able to define MIND
in spite of research of decades. Without defining MIND would it be possible to define
free will?
Vijay R. Joshi.
Source: Neuroscience vs. Philosophy http://archive.is/a0QeG
No comments:
Post a Comment